Thursday, April 27, 2017
Notes on Norman Kemp Smith's Kant: SPACE and TIME
All the mobilities stuff, it's all already here, in Kant. After wrapping up the preliminaries of the Transcendental Aesthetic in terms of first Space, and then Time (i.e. separately) we have a few pages on both (i.e. Space AND Time). Here's where the combination is introduced:
"Motion presupposes the perception of something movable. But in space, considered in itself, there is nothing movable; consequently the movable must be something that is found in space only through experience, and must therefore be an empirical datum. For the same reason, transcendental aesthetic cannot count the concept of alteration among its a priori data. Time itself does not alter, but only something which is in time. The concept of alteration thus presupposes the perception of something existing and of the succession of its determinations; that is to say, it presupposes experience" (Kant, 1989, page 82).
In other words space and time are analytically separate. Motion unites the two. This is quite a crucial point. We tend to think, however, in terms of space-travel when we think of motion, but it is useful to stick to Kant's original formulation of motion as fundamentally being about alteration. We alter spatial coordinates only through time; temporal coordinates only through space. Thinking time-travel, for example, H.G. Wells time-machine would never have worked because it did not move through space. Nahin has pointed out that Wells' time machine would collide with itself as soon as it started, causing a thermonuclear explosion (Nahin, 2011, page 64).
Now, if what Massey (2005) is getting at is that spacetimes are inherently relativistic and that Newtonian considerations are in error because of this (i.e. because they keep space and time separate), we can answer that not only are space and time properly kept analytically separate for philosophical purposes, they are also properly kept separate for everyday conceptions of space and time. These rely upon Newtonian mechanics and their representations.
A trace of your run depicted on Strava may have been generated by (relativistic) GPS signals, but the fact remains that you did not run anywhere near the speed of light. Even if you had, in both cases, (slow and near-light-speed running) can only be thought of in terms of representations of spacetime. They cannot be kept separate in any kind of 'alteration' as Kant would've put it because in motion space and time come together empirically, but not on a priori grounds. Alteration/motion is therefore analytically an a posteriori proposition.
Not only does Massey leave out the cognitive (bodily) basis for her metaphysics of space; she also leaves out the considerable imaginative and presuppositional content inherent to spatiotemporal considerations in geography. It is a lack of imagination that leads one down the dead-end path of non-representational theory. It is an a-theoretical text that takes on space without any reference to Kant (Thrift is almost guilty of this too).
This review is also a review of Adam Roberts (2005) The Thing Itself, and I have more to say about this brilliant work of science fiction. Its novum is strikingly original. I (in my admittedly limited capacity as sci-fi critic) can think of nothing like it in the genre. But perhaps that is due to its genre-defying capabilities. The Thing Itself is a Kant-machine for generating implications of taking the idea of the thing itself literally, and to its most logical conclusions. There are implications for space-time, which is why this review is wrapped up in a critique of non-representational geographical reason. The novum, in short, is the thing itself, as time-machine, as bomb, as computational enabler, and many other things, many of which are given their own distinct chapters for exploration. A couple of these chapters feel like short stories, but they feel no less like parts of a novel for that.
References:
Kant, Immanuel. 1989. Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan Education.
Massey, Doreen. 2005. For Space. London: Sage.
Nahin, Paul J. 2011. Time Travel: A Writer's Guide to the Real Science of Plausible Time Travel. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Roberts, Adam. 2015. The Thing Itself. London: Victor Gollancz.
Monday, April 24, 2017
Notes on Norman Kemp Smith's Kant: TIME
Maybe I'm reading too much into a novel. Maybe not. I find, reading Adam Roberts' brilliant science fiction novel The Thing Itself, that Roberts is following his own rule. That is, the one given in his guide to writing science fiction, also known as his Gold Rule: 'Show, don't tell' (Roberts, 2014).
The Thing Itself shows the reader (who, I posit, is in all probability a science fiction reader, and therefore more likely than most readers to be an active participant in the cultural milieu of the writer and potentially a writer him/her-self (Roberts, 2006)) what it means to construct a performatively heterogeneous world.
The world of The Thing Itself, as a heterogeneously performative one, is distinctly preferable to that of, for example, Doreen Massey in her book For Space, where she asserts that heterogeneity is something worth wanting in and of itself, and she asserts this without evidence, and as a statement, furthermore, with political intent.
Instead of a tedious quote from Massey, I will here assert with Kant (and Roberts) that heterogeneity is a property of the cognitive structure of being human and it is, furthermore, chalk-full of representational content that largely gives the structure its content. It is part of a dialectic of inside/outside that maps onto time/space quite precisely. The origin of this dialectic springs ultimately from the thing itself.
Roberts novel maps onto the Kantian dialectic very nicely, while at the same time producing a cognitively diverse set of responses to The Critique of Pure Reason (translation used by Roberts: unknown). There is, truing to the fundamental dialectic of the thing itself of Kant, a mix of the interior and the exterior in terms of the locale of narrativity of the various voices found in The Thing Itself. There are many. We switch, in ten chapters, between several with the longest being 'A Solid Gold Penny', corresponding to Kant's category of Limitation.
The beauty of the heterogeneous narrativity of The Thing Itself lies also in its compulsive readability. The cognitive structure of a main character corresponding to each 'fragment' chapter is set up and then fulfilled through the production of a stream of representations. In the Solid Gold Penny section, we have a sort of Molly Bloom cognition that is inhabited by a child who evolves through the course of the section to the point where this chapter alone constitutes a short story or mini-novel in itself.
There are alternating chapters that continue the thread of the ongoing conflict between Roy and Charles who become united in their opposition to an evil AI, product of 'The Institute' that has 'solved' the problem of 'the thing itself' by accessing it through computing devices that do not hold the same cognitive limitations as humans. They are thus able to directly access the thing itself because computer intelligences are not limited by the products of human evolution: brains structured specifically with underlying hardware that automatically 'see' the world structured in terms of time and space.
Time, in Roberts, is given as careful consideration as space, and it is structured logically according to various psychologies, times, and places in which the characters find themselves situated, from the 'olden days' of the Golden Coin chapter, to a futuristic one in which genders and times alike have become blurred almost beyond recognition. There is an experimental quality to these chapters that feels true somehow to the spirit of Kant, for whom time:
"is therefore to be regarded as real, not indeed as object but as the mode of representation of myself as object" (Kant, 1989, page 79).
I cannot help but think, when reading Massey (2005) that not only does she incessantly 'tell' (as opposed to showing), but that she completely misses the fundamental dialectic of space-time, that of the body and its structuring devices. She misses out too on the space-times of science fiction, as for example explained not only by Roberts himself (2006 and 2014), but by expert 'hard' science fiction writers like Nahin (2011), who demonstrate (i.e. 'show') what is and is not possible, logically and in light of the given theory and evidence, in time and space travel.
It is much more exciting to be told about space-time in a story like Roberts' The Thing Itself. I wish the reading (both popular and academic) portions of the world had more space (and time) for this kind of thing.
[To Be Continued]
References:
Kant, Immanuel. 1989. Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan Education.
Massey, Doreen. 2005. For Space. London: Sage.
Nahin, Paul J. 2011. Time Travel: A Writer's Guide to the Real Science of Plausible Time Travel. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Roberts, Adam. 2006. The History of Science Fiction. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Roberts, Adam. 2014. Get Started in Writing Science Fiction and Fantasy. London: John Murray.
Roberts, Adam. 2015. The Thing Itself. London: Victor Gollancz.
Friday, April 21, 2017
Notes on Norman Kemp Smith's Kant: SPACE
Space (Kant, 1989, pages 67-74)
Why are (as a colleague remarked to me in the hallway on the way to a meeting) so many geographers afraid to talk about space?
Perhaps they are afraid of becoming a bit like Roy Curtius in Roberts (2015, page 1) The Thing Itself: "Sick in the Head." Let's talk about Roy for a moment before returning to the pariah-status of space in the discipline of geography.
We find out in chapter 1 of The Thing Itself that Roy (antagonist) is stuck with Charles (protagonist) on a research base in Antarctica. It is just the two of them (a bit unlikely), and it turns out that Roy is a terrible roommate, a bit of a Sheldon Cooper know-it-all mixed together (as we find out later) with a Machiavellian silence-of-the-lambs side. Roy is reading the Meiklejohn translation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.
True, it is pretentious to read Kant (unless you are a Kant scholar or are writing a very cool novel based on his ideas), and to leave your copy of it lying around so people can see that you are reading Kant, and to discuss Kant with people who are not interested in it might be considered a sign of poor social skills or worse. Roy should have put me off reading Kant. However, it is Roberts novel as a whole that overwhelmingly corrected that negative reaction, way over towards a positive one, that of really really wanting to read the Critique now that I'd finished The Thing Itself.
To leave behind any doubt as to the coolness of reading Kant, and to throw it back in Roy's face, I decided (like, not long ago) that it was in fact the Meiklejohn translation that made people cray-cray when reading Kant, and not the fact of Kant himself. This, and reading Taylor's The Language Animal in which he cites the Smith translation, and the fact that the Smith translation is more in the spirit of Kant's self-description of the Critique as a literary (perhaps even more than a philosophical) undertaking, that I now thought to myself: I can handle this if I take it as a work of literature, and Smith's Kant seems to embody that notion.
Now when I say space has a pariah-status in the discipline of geography, this is true in spite of efforts of scholars like Massey (2005) and Soja (1989) to re-invigorate and liven-up the spatial. These efforts were (and are) necessary because geographers remain enamoured of place. But I would argue that Massey (but not so much Soja) in fact end up doing space a disservice by insisting on its non-representationality.
I have come (again) to pages 67-74 of Smith's Critique (Kant, 1989), the initiation to Kant's views on space, reaching a crescendo on pages 72-73. Without a doubt, Kant views space as a representation, to the extent that he almost equates the two (space/representation), except for the fact of its ideality. The is a massive exception to the 'rule' that space, in Kant, equals representation. In fact Kant makes it very clear (as does Roberts) that space as a 'substance' underlying objects out there in the world is no thing at all. Space is just an (shared, transcendental) idea that is part and parcel of what it means to be human, and not a property of the world itself.
Kant (1989) talks a lot, on pages 72-73 especially, about things-in-themselves, and it is here, I suspect, that the whole logic of Kant's dialectic is ultimately derived:
"we cannot treat the special conditions of sensibility as conditions of the possibility of things, but only of their appearances, we can indeed say that space comprehends all things that appear to us as external, but not all things in themselves..."
Take that NRT! Kant says, almost surreally, that space comprehends things. He (Kant, 1989) goes on to say:
"We assert, then, the empirical reality of space, as regards all possible outer experience; and yet at the same time we assert its transcendental ideality -- in other words, that it is nothing at all, immediately we withdraw the above condition, namely, its limitation to possible experience, and so look upon it as something that underlies things in themselves."
When Kant/Smith says that space is nothing at all, I immediately have doubts as to what extent Kant is the reactionary I have sometimes made him out to be! He sounds positively Thriftian (2007)!
So, here I am, at the edge of a conversion....to what? Back to NRT (no, for now)? To science fiction (I have been a sci-fi fan since adolescence, and The Thing Itself is a bit of a departure for me because I tend to favour hard/extrapolative sci-fi if I'm being honest)?
If there is any truth to the idea that mere repetition of words/phrases leads to belief in their validity/truth then Kant//Smith must've been aware of it, for we have a third mention (Kant, 1989, pages 73-74) in these two (and-a-half) pages of the thing itself:
"The transcendental concept of appearances in space, on the other hand, is a critical reminder that nothing intuited in space is a thing itself, that space is not a form inhering in things in themselves as their intrinsic property, that objects in themselves are quite unknown to us, and that what we call outer objects are nothing but mere representations of our sensibility, the form of which is space"
The problem now, is that Kant has to prove this, which is as it stands a mere assertion. At the same time, at least for now, this (Smith's) Kant is so immanently readable, so literary, that I was half the time thinking about writers like Cormac McCarthy, Christopher Dewdney, and Erin Moure (ok my taste in literature also runs smack into Canadian avant-garde poetry).
That is to say, I'm hooked, thanks in no small part to Roberts and Smith! Now, back to Kant.
[This is an ongoing review of Kant/Roberts, to be continued]
References:
Kant, Immanuel. 1989. Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan Education.
Massey, Doreen. 2005. For Space. London: Sage.
Roberts, Adam. 2015. The Thing Itself. London: Victor Gollancz.
Soja, Edward. 1989. Postmodern Geographies. London and New York: Verso.
Thrift, Nigel. 2007. Non-representational theory: space, politics, affect. Abingdon and New York: Routledge.
Thursday, April 20, 2017
Notes on Norman Kemp Smith's Kant
Introduction
There are two main inspirations for even beginning to think
about reading Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (i.e. the translation of
Kant made by Norman Kemp Smith). The
first was Charles Taylor’s book Hegel, which covers some of Kant (that part related
to dialectics). The second was Adam
Roberts’ book The Thing Itself, which gives a fictional treatment of the
Critique (though not the Kemp Smith version specifically).
Taylor also mentions Kant in his newer book The Language
Animal, citing Kemp’s translation specifically.
This was the final straw that broke my resistance to committing to
reading Kant’s most important work, translated by his most important
English-language translator. Taylor
himself has always had a big influence on my writing, in terms of both style
and content. Taylor's take on Kant (and
his translator) matters a great deal to counter-mapping mainly for getting
dialectics right. The latter requires
philosophical sophistication, subtlety, and style.
I’m also writing a book on dialectics that explicitly avoids
both Hegel and Marx. And without those
two elephants in the room, and with the above intellectual supports in place, I
can begin to think through some of the implications of Kant for my book (Contrapuntal
Cartographies) that takes a dialectical approach to counter-mapping. The latter, being properly dialectical and
therefore political, will undertake a constant excavation of taken-for-granted
assumptions and bases for the production of powerful mappings of- and
in-the-world.
In a way, I'm looking for a critique of non-representational
theory 'from the beyond', from before Hegel, Bergson, and Jameson launched
their critiques. A large part of the
continuing momentum of NRT is carried forward in the discipline of geography
with theorists like Massey and Thrift at the leading edge. Massey's For Space deals much too casually with questions of representation/space,
and her main point that space is seen as fixed and dead is somewhat close to
that made by Soja in 1989 in Postmodern Geographies.
So, reading Kemp's Kant is a way of critiquing the critique,
but also of being right at its leading edge as well. For counter-mapping, or mapping against
hegemony, it is the hegemony of NRT that is ripe for critique and
re-mapping. I propose to take a
more-than-representational approach that brings in evolutionary theories and
memetics, and also a good dose of dialectics (including Kant). An occasional geographer will be useful in
this endeavour (e.g. Lorimer's 2005 intervention in Progress in Human
Geography), but more often it will be philosophers, anthropologists, even
biologists I might disagree with (thinking Dawkins and indeed Kant here) who
will 'come to the rescue'. And then I'll
fold it all back into counter-mapping and geographical thought.
Philosopher Rowlands, in New Science of the Mind, and
anthropologist Malafouris, in How Things Shape the Mind, take on questions of
representation in ways that geographers do not seem ready to do. The all-too-easy geographical (NRT) critique
remains mired in post-structuralism and even, at times, a kind of
happy-go-lucky Nietzschean nihilism.
What Rowlands and Malafouris do, in their separate ways, is to give
questions of representation the treatment they deserve by carefully sifting
through the various arguments for and against, accepting and rejecting aspects
that do or do not fit the facts and frameworks at hand, and making judgements
and conclusions based only upon whether the theories fit the facts, without
speculation. In short, there is too much
speculation in geography.
Kant is just the medicine for the speculative turn in
geography, and for naive thinking in general (but also unfortunately in
geography very specifically). His
thinking is idealistic, which will also rub many geographers trained in
'materialities' and 'spatialities' thinking the wrong way, going against an
ingrained framework that is only superficially hard-headed. The problem with much recent theorising in
geography is in fact its lack of grounding in useful questions, in useful
theory! It is, in fact, (as for example
in McCormack's 2017 lead paper in Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers) an a-theoretical approach to questions of geography, lacking
robust empirical and methodological grounding, and epitomised by the
post-phenomenological, affective, speculative, and circumstantial, all terms
currently favoured in the current paradigm of geographical thought.
To put it another way: Kant's just the antidote.
Contrapuntal Cartographies: Dialectics of Counter-Mapping
(McGill-Queen's University Press) is expected to be on shelves by 2019
References:
Kant, Immanuel.
1989. Immanuel Kant's Critique of
Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith.
London: Macmillan Education.
Lorimer, Hayden.
2005. "Cultural geography:
the busyness of being `more-than-representational'" Progress in Human
Geography. 29(1): 83-94.
Malafouris, Lambros.
2013. How Things Shape the Mind:
A Theory of Material Engagement.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Massey, Doreen.
2005. For Space. London: Sage.
McCormack, Derek P.
2017. "The circumstances of
post-phenomenological life-worlds" Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers. 42(1): 2-13.
Roberts, Adam.
2015. The Thing Itself. London: Victor Gollancz.
Rowlands, Mark.
2010. The New Science of the
Mind: From Extended Mind to Embodied Phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Soja, Edward.
1989. Postmodern
Geographies. London and New York: Verso.
Taylor, Charles.
2016. The Language Animal: The
Full Shape of the Human Linguistic Capacity.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Taylor, Charles.
1975. Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)